210k views
5 votes
At face value for me these don't mean the same thing but I'm struggling to find if they are separate concepts. Are there examples where they differ? Are they or aren't they separate ideas? I can't fully articulate why (maybe coffee hasn't kicked in) not possible without and necessary for seem different, just that they feel different for metaphysical reasons. What inspired me to ask for more clarification was user Philip Klöcking's Kantian a priori basically is if that was not the case, the empirical knowledge we havewould not be possible. It is not a positively determined belief or proposition everybody shares.

As I wrote elsewhere, propositions a priori can be quite counter-intuitive. The a priori, ie. before all experience does bear a logical meaning in Kant. It means it is something that is logically prior to, a necessary condition of, experience.
Using your header, then, we can answer clearly: As soon as non-humans become cognisantof the necessary conditions of their experience, they can gain a priori knowledge. That is not the same as hard-wired, dogmatic beliefs, though.[1] Is everything which has something which makes it possible also following necessarily from that something? If I do equate them, am I buying into some metaphysics? Can we settle this without metaphysics? [1] Kant's modal semantics are rather novel, or he tried to make them out to be so, at any rate (he seems mostly successful, in my opinion; not that his position is confirmed beyond all doubt, but at least he was offering a relatively new idea). In the first Critique,he says at one point: Possibility, existence, and necessity nobody has ever yet been able to explain without being guilty of manifest tautology, when the definition has been drawn entirely from the pure understanding. For the substitution of the logical possibility of the conception—the condition of which is that it be not self-contradictory, for the transcendental possibility of things—the condition of which is that there be an object corresponding to the conception, is a trick which can only deceive the inexperienced.27 27In one word, to none of these conceptions belongs a corresponding object, and consequently their real possibility cannot be demonstrated, if we take away sensuous intuition—the only intuition which we possess—and there then remains nothing but the logical possibility, that is, the fact that the conception or thought is possible—which, however, is not the question; what we want to know being, whether it relates to an object and thus possesses any meaning. For Kant, even necessity is not a predicate. Ditto for possibility, for he says elsewhere that ahundred possible dollars (thalers) are not qualitatively different from a hundred real dollars. So when Kant says that his category-based principles are necessary,he is not speaking of the kind of free-floating necessity that theologians attached to God: Finally, as regards the third postulate, it applies to material necessity in existence, and not to merely formal and logical necessity in the connection of conceptions. Now as we cannot cognize completelya priorithe existence of any object of sense, though we can do so comparativelya priori, that is, relatively to some other previously given existence—a cognition, however, which can only be of such an existence as must be contained in the complex of experience, of which the previously given perception is a part—the necessity of existence can never be cognized from conceptions, but always, on the contrary, from its connection with that which is an object of perception. But the only existence cognized, under the condition of other given phenomena, as necessary, is the existence of effects from given causes in conformity with the laws of causality. It is consequently not the necessity of the existence of things (as substances), but the necessity of the state of things that we cognize, and that not immediately, but by means of the existence of other states given in perception, according to empirical laws of causality. Further reading:Transcendental Arguments (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy). a) Not possible without suggests a strong dependency leading to impossibility, while necessary for implies a requirement without explicitly suggesting impossibility without it.
b)Kant's a priori knowledge refers to logical elements necessary for empirical knowledge, not necessarily equating to hard-wired or dogmatic beliefs.
c) Kant's view on necessity and possibility in relation to empirical knowledge involves a complex interplay of existence, perception, and causality, emphasizing necessity in states of things rather than existence itself.

User Nate Rubin
by
8.7k points

1 Answer

5 votes

Final answer:

Kant's philosophy suggests that certain innate cognitive categories are necessary to process and understand empirical experience, though they themselves are not empirically derived. They serve as preconditions for making empirical knowledge possible, linking the 'necessary for' with the notion of 'not possible without' in the context of epistemology.

Step-by-step explanation:

The concepts of 'necessary for' and 'not possible without' are indeed different, but they intersect within the realm of epistemology, the study of knowledge. According to Immanuel Kant's philosophy, certain innate categories are necessary for constructing empirical knowledge. These categories, such as causation and substance, are not derived from experience; instead, they are preconditions that make experience intelligible. While empirical knowledge itself is about direct experiences, the categories that shape this knowledge are not experienced directly, but are applied to our experience, making empirical judgments possible.

In simpler terms, we can think of these categories like a mathematical formula that is necessary for solving a specific type of problem—not directly observable, but essential for making sense of the problem. A priori knowledge, such as mathematical truths, can be regarded as necessary for understanding certain empirical facts, even if that knowledge is first encountered through experience, like learning multiplication tables. Kant combines rationalism and empiricism by asserting that, while we acquire empirical knowledge through experience, our innate cognitive structure is necessary to process and understand that experience.

User Masika
by
8.0k points